Home
/
RELIGION & LIBERTY ONLINE
/
Who Is a Libertarian?
Who Is a Libertarian?
Jan 9, 2025 7:02 AM

It’s plicated than you think. A new book takes a detailed look at all the peting definitions, and enormous resources that the libertarian movement brings to discussions of a free market and a free people.

Read More…

In their new book, The Individualists: Radicals, Reactionaries, and the Struggle for the Soul of Libertarianism, Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi have created an exhaustive and fascinating history of the libertarian movement and its animating philosophies. While for many, the term hardly existed before Ron Paul made them Google it, the movement itself actually begins in the mid-19th century, building upon classical liberal thought dating back to the mid-18th century, and wields far more tangible influence than is often supposed. It’s fitting that philosophers who refer to themselves as “bleeding heart libertarians” should pen such a work. They do not shy away from describing the most radical forms libertarianism has taken while maintaining a laudable sensitivity to salient critiques of the movement, even in its softened forms. The pels more than it would if the authors were making their case for their own version of libertarianism. Instead, they honestly represent all sides, including critiques of “bleeding heart libertarians” such as themselves as possibly apostate, with refreshing frankness.

To begin, “primordial” mid-19th-century libertarianism arose as a reaction to socialism in Britain and France, but also as a radical reaction to slavery, imperial war, and large, corrupt business interests. As the threat of real-world, massive state experiments munism loomed, libertarians shifted gears significantly to align themselves with conservatives. Some of the more creative forms of libertarianism, like the libertarian socialism and economic mutualism of Benjamin Tucker (1854–1939), consequently disappeared. But ever since the Soviet threat crumbled in 1991, libertarianism has split between the bleeding hearts—more aligned with the social justice left—and the cultural reactionaries—more aligned with the right (even the alt-right in some cases). Then there are those who see themselves as uncategorizable on the left-right spectrum because their alignment changes depending on the issue.

As our authors work their way through various libertarian debates, we are introduced to a fascinating cast of characters. The importance of Richard Cobden (1804­–1865) cannot be overstated, especially for Americans. He played a profound role in the formation of people like William Lloyd Garrison, Harriett Beecher Stowe, and Frederick Douglass. Nor do our authors shy away from the profound effect of Christianity on these writers’ aversion to abuse of power. As odd as it may seem today, bringing an end to the Corn Laws in England (protectionist tariffs on many internationally traded items) was the precursor and template for bringing an end to slavery in America.

Of course, not everyone in the es off as heroically as Cobden and Douglass. Lew Rockwell, founder and president of the Mises Institute, has played an outsize role in the late-20th-century libertarian movement but also seems to relish indulging in explicitly racist and conspiratorial thinking. Since the question of whether libertarianism has the resources, or even the concern, to address historical injustices such as the oppression of Black Americans, the popularity of figures like Rockwell and his colleague Hans-Hermann Hoppe raises legitimate concerns. On the other hand, the central part that libertarians played in the actual abolition of slavery, as well as later when folks like Moorfield Storey at the NAACP and Rose Wilder Lane at the Pittsburgh Courier fought hard for the individual rights of Black Americans, discourages the reader from writing off the movement on such grounds.

Zwolinski and Tomasi elucidate six main signifiers of libertarianism, outlining a movement they refer to as “inherently flexible.” While this description of libertarianism will surprise many Twitter anarchists who claim the label exclusively for themselves, the detailed history of libertarian thinkers makes it clear that the debate between anarchists and minimal statists has been a live question the entire time. The six core ideas are:

IndividualismPrivate propertySkepticism of authorityFree marketsSpontaneous orderNegative liberty

Of course, each core idea gives rise to its own set of clarifications and debates. One need not be a metaphysical individualist to be a methodological individualist, for instance. A libertarian may believe that collective entities (such as families or cultures) are real while maintaining that only individuals make choices, and therefore only individuals can be held morally responsible. The plaint about America’s culture of individualism and lack munity could, then, be laid at the feet of a certain kind of libertarianism. plaint, I assume, develops in light of a cultural concern about lonely or isolated people who e morally malformed. Yet consider how a libertarian critique of the state might actually concur with such a concern: the “crowd-out” effect means that faceless government provisions of social services takes the place of organic civil society solutions—the church, family, and nonprofit worlds—thus weakening those institutions and separating individuals from their natural context munity.

Private property, too, is subject to various debates. Is the property we own now just? Some say private property rights rely on an unbroken chain of just exchanges going all the way back to the creation of the goods themselves. But you and I both know that the majority of the things we own are not the result of such a chain of exchanges, but rather of violence and theft that shifted property to its non-rightful owners (consider Europeans’ expropriation of Native American lands). If all current property is unjust in this way, how shall it be redistributed? On the other hand, property rights could be grounded in a general agreement that there is no way to know or agree on what is perfectly, cosmically just, but that honoring long possession is an appealing way to settle the question without violence. This option does not rule out correcting historical wrongs, but almost certainly limits such corrections to recent history, in which clear records can be found and victims identified.

Skepticism of authority is yet another mitment requiring some clarification. Many libertarians passionately support parental authority, for instance, up to the usual limits, such as physical abuse. Others are quite excited at the prospect of very munities (like the Amish) forming as long as they are small enough to make leaving a genuine option—Nozick’s “utopia of utopias.” The authority about which all libertarians are highly skeptical is the authority of the state—because it is the entity making a monopoly claim on the legitimate use of violence. es through clearly in the book is that, at its heart, libertarianism is a philosophy that resists coercion to the greatest extent possible. It doesn’t require pacifism, as libertarians believe in the right to defend oneself. But any coercion must be justified in terms of the defense against harm. Of course, important questions will arise: What counts as harm? Can we use force to solve the coordination problem in defending ourselves against aggression by states or by criminals? These questions lie at the heart of the debate between anarchists and minimal statists. Zwolinski and Tomasi are careful to note that classical liberals are less strict in this regard, and more likely to approve of the use of state power to solve problems that are not strictly a matter of harm, such as the public provision of education or various forms of basic welfare like Milton Freidman’s negative e tax. At the same time, it ought to be acknowledged that genuine public goods problems and externalities problems are cases of dealing with genuine harm, such as pollution. So one need not fall outside the libertarian umbrella if one defends state intervention to address such harms, but only if one also maintains a healthy skepticism about the state’s likelihood of doing so well or fairly.

A discussion of free markets is especially helpful to deal with the more recent association of libertarians with a defense of capitalism. Libertarians are fairly consistent in their condemnation of what we might call crony capitalism: the practice of well-established businesses using state-enforced regulations, subsidies, or other advantages to shut out petitors. This violates the spirit of the free market, which democratizes the economy by letting consumers choose the winners and losers. As I often say to my students, the market is a profit and loss system. We have to let businesses fail to allow it to function properly. But libertarians who are not actual anarchists do legitimately run into problems here. Excepting perhaps the period after Richard Cobden was able to get the Corn Laws repealed, there’s never been a truly free market to speak of. As public choice theory explains (and Zwolinski and Tomasi summarize beautifully), so long as politicians wield the power of the state, they can set up a system of favoritism toward their friends. This makes the poor poorer and the rich richer—hardly what Adam Smith envisioned for a flourishing economy. If cronyism is so unavoidable, then perhaps the leftist critiques of capitalist abuse of power are patible with a radical libertarian critique of the state. The only alternative, as Churchill might say, is pare this system with all the others. A mostly free market with a libertarian contingency vigilantly fighting cronyism may simply be the best we can pull off this side of the kingdom of God.

Spontaneous order (sometimes referred to as emergent order), interestingly enough, may be the one core idea on the list that doesn’t require much clarification beyond a definition. The right set of reliably defended fundamental rules, like property rights, contracts, and equal protection before the law, will lead to the blossoming of billions of mutually advantageous exchanges. People will simply do this. Prices allow us to allocate resources efficiently without a central planner, who doesn’t have the information to run an economy anyway. The only real controversies around the spontaneous order concept are whether the fundamental rules are also spontaneous orders, and what to do about bad cultural movements—like racism—that might also be described as spontaneous orders. It seems clear to me that mon law is both the source of our own legal system of rights and protections and a clear case of emergent legal norms that grounded an even plex economic enrichment. While it is almost certainly the case that there has to be enough cultural capital in place for citizens to adhere to liberal norms, it’s not clear whether the implementation of the laws has to be as emergent for others as it was for us Americans. Perhaps Milton Friedman’s controversial support for Pinochet’s economic policies is an example of this idea at work. Friedman’s logic was that since his students could convince the dictator to put basic economic freedoms in place, it would not only lead to more economic growth but also to the flourishing of more civil freedoms. However, Freidman later regretted his assumption that economic freedom would translate into political and religious freedom, as have many in the libertarian movement. The artificial imposition of free market principles by a dictator did indeed make Chile rich, but it did not reorient the country toward more freedom. In fact, Pinochet killed thousands of his own citizens and corruptly amassed tens of millions of dollars in wealth. Examples like Singapore and—at least temporarily—even China have shown that authoritarian governments can take advantage of the efficiency of economic freedom while continuing to subjugate citizens on every other measure. The only possible counterargument to giving up the long-held libertarian belief that free trade would lead to greater freedom in general is that we might see the libertarian vision of full freedom realized eventually. After all, some populations may simply not be as culturally attuned to individual freedom in matters of, say, religion but may e more so over time, as the natural cosmopolitanism of international trade makes cultural hegemony increasingly impossible.

Finally, libertarians see liberty as primarily negative, that is, as a matter of being free from interference. I may be too poor to take a vacation to Disneyland, but this does not limit my freedom, according to a negative concept of liberty. No one has stopped me from going; my inability to go is simply a matter of circumstance. In contrast, welfare liberals may argue that certain positive freedoms must be guaranteed in order to make any negative freedom meaningful. No, I need not go to Disneyland to enjoy my liberty, but I do need to eat on a regular basis and not die of treatable diseases to enjoy it. In what sense am I genuinely free if I am so desperate to sustain myself, for instance, that I must accept whatever employment e my way? I may be left, realistically, with only one choice—or worse, none. One way to escape this problem is to think of the negative view of liberty as a systemic, not individual, matter. Which system is more likely to put the poor in a position to enjoy their negative liberty? One that guarantees these basic goods but as a result stifles economic growth in general? Or one with a high level of economic dynamism and thick civil society institutions such that very few are ever left in such a position? Of course, going this route turns the question into an empirical one, rather than a principled one. And even if libertarians are correct that the more dynamic market will create far fewer impoverished citizens, it does not mean that contemporary citizens of developed countries are willing to let the few remaining slip through the cracks. F.A. Hayek himself, of Road to Serfdom fame, declared that once a country gains a certain level of wealth it es simply intolerable to allow people to die on the street. In the end, the less purist in the libertarian movement have offered more efficient and dignifying alternatives to the welfare state, such as a negative e tax or pure cash transfers, to replace the paternalistic and byzantine system of targeted programs we have today. Ultimately, though, any non-anarchist libertarian will have to face the reality that liberty cannot be entirely negative. After all, even to have a reasonable system of courts, we must show up for jury duty. Thus, the right to a fair trial is a positive right, demanding some sacrifice on the part of all citizens.

Of course, I have my quibbles with The Individualists, as anyone would with a book that covers so much ground in such a pithy manner. I was a bit surprised to hear that Locke “merely asserts” the concept of self-ownership. I had been under the impression that because God (whose existence Locke believes to be provable) made us, we belong to Him as a matter of the Doctrine of Maker’s Right, which is intuitively true. So technically we are self-stewards, not self-owners, which is why, for instance, we must not kill ourselves. But as a kind of philosophical shorthand, we can refer to ourselves as self-owners, since we know prehension of the natural law that God requires us to care for ourselves, and only each individual can control him- or herself. But I am ready to be corrected if I am wrong. I also wouldn’t refer to David Hume as a utilitarian. Hume is certainly a consequentialist, but nowhere in his work does he speak of aggregating utility. When Hume uses the term “public utility,” he means the expansion of the space within which more mutually advantageous exchanges are possible between individuals and groups. Since the aggregation of our preferences, and therefore a kind of implicit majoritarianism, is both the most opprobrious and the least logically defensible part of utilitarian ethics, I hated to see him lumped in with that crowd. But once again, these may be merely semantic matters.

Overall, I found The Individualists not prehensive also but well-organized and conversationally written, required reading for everyone in the liberty movement and of interest, I would think, to political philosophers and theorists, as well as adjacent groups such as free market conservatives and anti-statist leftists. In short, The Individualist was an immensely enjoyable, informative, and enlightening read.

Comments
Welcome to mreligion comments! Please keep conversations courteous and on-topic. To fosterproductive and respectful conversations, you may see comments from our Community Managers.
Sign up to post
Sort by
Show More Comments
RELIGION & LIBERTY ONLINE
Work As Worship
Do you view the work you do each day as worship, or is it something you do to pass the time or merely collect a paycheck? Remember work is not only the actions you perform to obtain a pay check, but includes any action “people do to earn a living.” Signs indicate that evangelical practice is entrapped in a dangerous snare of limitation placence. By placing almost sole emphasis on Bible study, worship attendance, and giving/tithing — the churchly aspects...
Wringing Hands Over Dominionism
Michelle Goldberg has a column up at the aptly named Daily Beast letting us all know that we really need to worry about something called “Dominionism” which supposedly prevails among Michelle Bachmann, Rick Perry, and folks who support their campaigns. Reinhold Niebuhr once warned of the dangers of religious illiteracy. Here we have exhibit A. Goldberg claims Bachmann and Perry are “deeply associated” with this “theocratic strain” of Christian fundamentalism. Yes, they are probably so deeply associated with it that...
New Amsterdam Redivivus
As part of our ongoing engagement with the Protestant world, the Acton Institute has taken on the translation of Abraham Kuyper’s Common Grace, under the general editorship of Stephen Grabill and in partnership with Kuyper College. We’re convinced that renewed interest in the thought of Abraham Kuyper (1837-1920), and in fact rediscovering aspects of his thought that have been lost or misconstrued in the intervening decades, is critically important for the reconstruction of Protestant social thought. So it’s a big...
Progressive Boot Firmly Planted on Ranchers’ Throats
More than a billion dollars has already been pledged to relieve victims of the drought-turned-famine ravaging the Horn of Africa. The stricken countries—Somalia in particular—do not have the technology and the infrastructure to deal with a major drought, and so in what is ing a regular occurrence, the West is stepping in with aid. Meanwhile back at the ranch, Texas and Oklahoma are suffering record droughts that are wiping out crops and taxing cattle businesses. Ranchers cannot rely on the...
Another Run at the “Dominionism” Meme
In my last post, I rejected the contention by Michelle Goldberg and others that evangelical leaders such as Michelle Bachmann and Rick Perry are significantly influenced by the aims of the tiny Christian Reconstructionism movement. I tried to make the point that CR has a negligible political influence on evangelicals and that it is not honest to view evangelical office holders and candidates in the light of CR’s aims. The entire thing, I think, is a tar baby sort of...
TV Bias Book Not Ready for Primetime
My contribution to this week’s Acton News & Commentary: TV Bias Book Not Ready for Primetime By Bruce Edward Walker Reading Ben Shapiro’s Primetime Propaganda: The True Hollywood Story of How the Left Took Over Your TV is similar to time traveling through the pages of a TV Guide. Dozens of television series from the past 50 years are dissected through Shapiro’s conservative lens – or, at least, what passes for Shapiro’s brand of conservatism – to reveal his perception...
Krugman: Aliens Worth More to Economy than Men and Women (VIDEO)
Paul Krugman made the mistake of over-sharing this past weekend when he told CNN’s Fareed Zakaria he thinks that the United States economy would benefit from a military build-up to fight made-up space aliens. He’s been defended as being fed up with Republican obstructionism, being desperate to make a point, or even being wholly pletely correct. He’s entirely wrong though, and his thinking (what there is of it) is an example of the kind of depersonalized economics that has cost...
World Youth Day: Pope talks profits and people
On his flight to World Youth Day in Madrid this morning, Pope Benedict XVI responded to a question about the current economic crisis. Not sure what the question was, but the well-respected Italian Vatican analyst Andrea Tornielli captured the reply. Here’s my quick translation of the Pope’s answer: The current crisis confirms what happened in the previous grave crisis: the ethical dimension is not something external to economic problems but an internal and fundamental dimension. The economy does not function...
AP: International Aid Actually Worsens Somali Food Crisis
It’s terribly sad, but you just can’t make this stuff up: Thousands of sacks of food aid meant for Somalia’s famine victims have been stolen and are being sold at markets in the same neighborhoods where skeletal children in filthy refugee camps can’t find enough to eat, an Associated Press investigation has found. As much as half of the food aid going into Somalia is stolen and sold in markets. Militants that control of large parts of the country and...
Religions’ reactions to financial realities
John Baden, chairman of the Foundation for Research on Economics & the Environment in Bozeman, Mont., wrote a column for the August 19 Bozeman Daily Chronicle about the Circle of Protection and Christians for a Sustainable Economy and how each has formulated a very different faith witness on the federal budget and debt debate. Baden says that the CASE letter to President Obama is “quite remarkable for it reads like one written by respected economists and policy analysts.” I attended...
Related Classification
Copyright 2023-2025 - www.mreligion.com All Rights Reserved