Home
/
RELIGION & LIBERTY ONLINE
/
Swinburne on God and morality
Swinburne on God and morality
Sep 16, 2025 7:35 AM

Last week I attended a lecture on the campus of Calvin College given by Richard Swinburne, Emeritus Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the Christian Religion, University of Oxford. His lecture was titled, “God and Morality,” and was the fourth in a series of lectures for a summer seminar, “Science, Philosophy, and Belief.” The seminar was focused on the development of Chinese professors and posgraduate students, and included lectures by Sir John Polkinghorne, Alvin Plantinga, and Owen Gingerich.

Swinburne, who is a convert from Anglicanism to Orthodoxy, has recently turned his attention to questions of morality, having previously dealt with most every aspect of the philosophy of religion. I will not attempt a summary of his presentation here. The lecture has been digitally archived on the seminar site (downloadable MP3 here), and ments and critiques I offer below will best be understood after having listened to the presentation yourself.

Swinburne’s list of publications includes a ing article, “What Difference Does God Make to Morality?” in Is Goodness without God Good Enough?: A Debate on Faith, Secularism, and Ethics, ed. R.K. Garcia and N.L. King (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2008), scheduled for release in October of this year later this month. This article will presumably present a similar case as appeared in Swinburne’s lecture.

I must say that the fact that I feel I have to construct alternative readings of Swinburne’s case is rather disappointing. This need may simply be attributable to my own failings, in which case the readings I explore below are unlikely to be helpful. But I do think it is the case that Swinburne’s presentation was unclear, in the sense that his terminological usages were often equivocal and there was not a consistent line of reasoning, as far as I could see. That is, the ways in which he attempted to support the five basic claims of his argument sometimes had no clear relation to the claims themselves. This will e more clear as I explore the alternative reading to Swinburne’s first claim.

It seems to me that there are two basic ways to understand Swinburne’s argument as presented in this lecture. The first is the one that I believe makes the most sense, but alas, I do not believe for reasons I will highlight below that this simpler reading captures the extent of what Swinburne intends. After I outline this first, more convincing but less likely, reading, I will outline what I believe Swinburne is actually attempting to claim.

This first reading is more convincing in part because it does not claim as much as the alternative reading. Rather, on this reading I understand Swinburne to be making primarily, if not solely, epistemological claims about our knowledge of God and morality. Thus, when his first claim is summarized as, “God makes no difference to what are the necessary moral truths,” we could gloss that as meaning, “Our belief in the existence of God makes no difference as to whether or not we believe there are necessary moral truths.” This seems to fit with the sort of evidence Swinburne marshals in support of this first claim, because he chiefly talks about how e to know moral truths (through moral formation and instruction via authority), and concludes that whether or not our parents, for example, instruct us as theists or atheists, they instruct us to believe in moral truths.

On this epistemological reading, as I shall call it, Swinburne proceeds to fill out what epistemological difference a belief in God makes regarding our conception of moral truths. Thus, his second point, “God makes a great difference to what are the contingent moral truths,” can be read as meaning that whether or not we believe in God will have a great consequence for what we conceive contingent moral truths to consist in. Further, his third point, “God makes a great difference to the seriousness of morality,” would mean that our belief in the existence of God (or lack thereof) has a necessary impact on how weighty certain moral values are to us.

Swinburne’s fourth point is the most clearly epistemological, as it has to do with the relation of revelation to our understanding of the grounding of morality. Essentially Swinburne claims that a prophet whose revelation has been legitimized by some miraculous sign will e an authoritative source for imparting knowledge about the moral order. Swinburne concludes by offering some suggestions as to why God might issue particular mands.

As I said earlier, I believe this reading is both more convincing and that it presents a less controversial claim than the alternative reading I will present below. I also believe that the internal evidence and the flow of the argument points to the likelihood that this second reading is closer to what Swinburne actually intends.

This alternative reading understands Swinburne to be chiefly attempting to make ontological claims about the status of the moral order in relation to God. Thus, when he claims in his first section that “God makes no difference to what are the necessary moral truths,” we should read this rather straightforwardly as claiming that the existence of God makes no difference with regard to the existence of necessary moral truths. In some sense, these necessary moral truths, by virtue of their necessity, exist independently from God. If all we had to go on was Swinburne’s defense of this claim in the first part, we would most certainly be pressed to understand it as an epistemological (the first reading) rather than an ontological (the second reading) claim.

But in his explanation of his second claim, Swinburne seems to clarify the earlier claim by noting that it is particularly God’s will that makes “no difference to what are the necessary moral truths.” In this second part I believe Swinburne, intentionally or not, is positioning himself within an intellectualist stream of metaphysical thought. Indeed, if his overall argument is read as making ontological claims, then it resembles in many ways the so-called “impious hypothesis.”

The most famous instance of the impious hypothesis occurs in the prolegomena to Hugo Grotius’ De jure belli et pacis, where he writes concerning his articulation of the natural law, “What we have been saying would have a degree of validity even if we should concede that which cannot be conceded without the utmost wickedness, that there is no God, or that the affairs of men are of no concern to Him” (§11). This saying has been attributed to Grotius as an innovation, and used as a basis for historical arguments for secular versions of natural law. This historiographical trend continues to the present day, and can be found in works like Randy Barnett, “A Law Professor’s Guide to Natural Law and Natural Rights,” Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 20 (1997): 659.

More careful historical research has shown that this impious hypothesis is not an innovation in Grotius, but rather part of a longer tradition of argumentation, dating at least back to the later middle ages, and is generally characteristic of an intellectualist account of natural law as opposed to a voluntarist account. See, for instance, the ments of Francis Oakley, “Grotius’s impious hypothesis can be seen to witness less to any great secular novelty than to the continuing dialectic between two distinct theories concerning the metaphysical grounding of natural law which the early modern natural law thinkers had inherited from their medieval and late medieval predecessors” (Natural Law, Laws of Nature, Natural Rights: Continuity and Discontinuity in the History of Ideas [New York: Continuum, 2005], 66).

N. E. Simmonds gives a good account of the impious hypothesis in his article, “Grotius and Pufendorf” in A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, although as my colleague Stephen Grabill has noted, his emphasis on Suarez as an immediate source for Grotius’ theory bears little direct evidence in Grotius’ own writings. And, indeed, it may be that Suarez’s influence was mediated through some other figure, perhaps Arminius, who was himself influenced by Suarez in no small measure.

In any case, to return to the matter at hand, to my eyes Swinburne’s case echoes in great part the impious hypothesis, which cannot be read as merely making an epistemological claim. We might also note in passing that Swinburne refers to the Euthyphro dilemma, which is monplace reference used to raise the ontological question of the grounding of the moral order, whether in natural law or mand. See Nathan Gilmore’s astute observations about the facile move between the polytheistic situation in Euthyphro’s dialogue to its relevance to a discussion in classical monotheism.

I’ll conclude by noting that the particularly epistemological character of Swinburne’s fourth point regarding revelation makes it seem more plausible that he means to make ontological points in the other sections. On this second and alternative reading, then, Swinburne, whom another colleague has characterized a holding to a tritheistic Arian position (see Nathan Jacobs, “On ‘Not Three Gods’–Again: Can a Primary-Secondary Substance Reading of Ousia and Hypostasis avoid Tritheism?” Modern Theology 24, no. 3 [July 2008]: 345), is arguing for something like an intellectualist account of God and an eternal moral order that is somehow and in some sense independent of at least the divine will, and perhaps even God himself.

Comments
Welcome to mreligion comments! Please keep conversations courteous and on-topic. To fosterproductive and respectful conversations, you may see comments from our Community Managers.
Sign up to post
Sort by
Show More Comments
RELIGION & LIBERTY ONLINE
Why Such Hostility About Religious Liberty?
In a nation founded upon (at least in part) the ability to practice one’s religious beliefs without government interference, we Americans are in a weird spot. It seems that everywhere we turn, folks who practice their religious beliefs are under assault. Again, weird, since most of us who do practice our faith don’t try to cram it down anyone’s throat. Even groups like the Jehovah’s Witnesses – well-known for their door-to-door proselytizing – are happy to step off your front...
Trickle-Down Welfare Economics?
Over at NRO, Thomas Sowell takes on what he calls the “lie” of “trickle-down economics.” Thus, writes Sowell, “the ‘trickle-down’ lie is 100 percent lie.” Sowell cites Bill de Blasio and Barack Obama as figures perpetuating the “lie,” along with writers in “theNew York Times, in theWashington Post, and by professors at prestigious American universities — and even as far away as India.” But we should also note that “trickle-down theories” get a mention in Evangelii Gaudium, too: “some people...
Restaurant Owner with Down Syndrome Shares His Gift
At 14 years old, Tim Harris dreamed of owning his own restaurant. He was born with Down syndrome, sohis parents weren’t quite sure what to think.Yet soon after Tim began his first job as a host at Red Robin, it all started to make sense. “[Customers] were visibly happy to see him and Tim really developed a following,” saysKeith Harris, Tim’s father. “People e to the restaurant specifically when he was working. As we sat there, we started thinking about...
Virtue At GQ: The Heart of ‘Look Sharp, Live Smart’
One of the most popular blog posts at Gentlemen’s Quarterly Magazine (GQ) in 2013 was mentary giving men 10 reasons to stop viewing pornography. On GQ’s website the piece registered 24,000 thousand “like” on Facebook in just a few weeks. The popularity of the post could be a signal that Americans really are interested in discussing moral issues and perhaps GQ should take advantage of this opportunity to include more posts that offer moral direction even if some might ultimately...
‘Out of Darkness:’ U.S. Catholic Bishops Declare National Migration Week
The United States Conference of Catholic Bishops (USCCB) has declared January 5-11, 2014 as National Migration Week, with the theme of “Out of Darkness.” The USCCB states that this “vulnerable” population needs support, protection and prayerful ministry in order to thrive. The USCCB outlines four major groups of immigrants: migrant children, undocumented immigrants, refugees, and victims of human trafficking. Each group has very different needs; the most vulnerable, the bishops say, are migrant children. Dependent on others for food, shelter,...
Christmas Does Not Consist in an Abundance of Possessions
Reading this profile of UPS’s “Mr. Peak,” Scott Abell, is an enlightening exercise, particularly after the close of this holiday season. Mr. Peak is the guy in charge of making sure that the thing you ordered the Friday before Christmas gets there by Christmas Eve. Or as Devin Leonard puts it, “It’s e so easy for people to shop puters and smartphones that they frequently delay their purchases until the last minute. Mr. Peak’s job, in effect, is to fulfill...
Now Available: ‘On Righteousness, Oaths, and Usury’ by Wolfgang Musculus
Christian’s Library Press has released a new translation of Wolfgang mentary on Psalm 15, which includes two related appendices on the topics of oaths and usury. Released at the end of 2013, On Righteousness, Oaths, and es on the 450th anniversary of Musculus’ passing. The book is part of CLP’s growing series, Sources in Early Modern Economics, Ethics, and Law. Musculus (1497–1563)was a second-generation reformer in the cities of Strasbourg, Augsburg, and Bern, and produced a variety of works, including...
Let’s Define ‘Income Inequality’
The saga of e inequality” stretches on. The young people of the Occupy Wall Street movement now have a website, and President Obama has proclaimed it the “defining issue of our time.” But what IS it exactly? Does it mean that a teacher, a brain surgeon and a garbage collector should all earn the same wage? Does it mean the wealthy entrepreneur should simply give away her money, rather than investing it or leaving it to her heirs? American Enterprise...
When Bellow Met Chambers
You may have heard that Ayn Rand really disliked C.S. Lewis. But do you know what happened when Saul Bellow met Whittaker Chambers? Bellow’s biographer James Atlas provides the anecdote. The context is that Bellow has very nearly gotten a reporting job at Time magazine via Dana Tasker, an editor there. It a gig that would mean a real windfall for the struggling author: There was just one hurdle–a formality, Tasker assured him. He would have to see Whittaker Chambers,...
What is the Most Important Factor in Improving Education?
What is the key to improving education in America? Stuart Buck says that Barker Bausell’s book, Too Simple to Fail: A Case for Educational Change, provides the answer: His main thesis: that the only thing that improves education is spending more time on instruction at a given child’s level. In his words: All school learning is explained in terms of the amount of relevant instructional time provided to a student. That’s it: more time + suitability for a child’s level....
Related Classification
Copyright 2023-2025 - www.mreligion.com All Rights Reserved