Home
/
RELIGION & LIBERTY
/
Scrutinising Scruton
Scrutinising Scruton
Sep 18, 2024 6:36 PM

  It has been four years since Sir Roger Scruton passed away, leaving a significant gap within the sphere of intellectual conservatism. The void is evident due to the undeniable impact that Scruton had, earning him the title of one of the best-known British conservative philosophers at the onset of the new century. This recognition stems not only from the importance of his ideas but also from his role as a pivotal figure in popularising conservatism within political, academic, and social discourse. He achieved this through his academic and popular writing, an active public intellectual life, his editorship of the Salisbury Review, and his activism in Central Europe, which garnered him animosity from all the right quarters.

  Despite Scrutons near-universal adulation within conservative circles across the West, certain quarters of Britains conservative tradition identified some issues with his interpretation of conservatism. For instance, Scruton recounted that Maurice Cowling considered the project to construct a philosophy of conservatism as naive, since the doctrine is rooted in history and practical considerations. Furthermore, Cowling, focusing on Scrutons editorship of the Salisbury Review argued that it represented “the nearest intellectually reputable thing that England has had to the authoritarian Conservatism which de Maistre, in a Christian, and Maurras in a post-Christian, mode had propagated in France. Cowlings words imply that Scrutonian conservatism has more in common with continental conservatism than with the British tradition. Consequently, Cowlings reservation about Scrutons take on conservatism points to the difference between what the former labelled as the Peterhouse and Scrutonian Right.

  Cowlings reservations were also echoed by what he labelled the LSE Right, particularly by one of its most active members, Kenneth Minogue. Minogue and Scruton were acquainted through their participation in Shirley Letwins salon, meetings of the Conservative Philosophy Group, and, in the words of Scruton, the many occasions when we would find ourselves signed up to this or that initiative, institution, or campaign that we both believed in. Despite their involvement in intellectual groups and conservative political campaigns, they rarely engaged with each other intellectually about conservatism in the public sphere. However, in reviewing George Watson’s book, The Idea of Liberalism, Minogue made a passing critique of Scruton. Minogue wrote that Scruton’s conservatism “suggests the radicalism of the 1960s” and shares with the revolutionary a “dogmatic conviction that there is only one right path in politics,” which is significantly divergent from “anything that might be called conservative in Oakeshott.

  Minogues words offer an initial insight into his reservations regarding Scrutonian conservatism. First, by discerning between Oakeshott and Scruton, Minogue elucidates the distinctive character of the LSE Rights conservatism. Furthermore, considering Oakeshotts status as a prominent British conservative thinker, Minogues disassociation of Scruton from Oakeshott suggests that Scrutonian conservatism lies outside the British tradition. Lastly, Minogue contends that Scrutonian conservatism, by implying radicalism and prescribing a singular correct approach in politics, inherently exhibits ideological tendencies.

  Minogues latter critique holds significant importance, particularly in contrast to the views of conservative thinkers such as Russell Kirk, who have consistently emphasised that conservatism is not an ideology. However, Minogue assigns a specific meaning to ideology, defining it as “a comprehensive diagnosis of the fundamental evil of the modern world, which further explains how that evil is to be cured.” As I have previously discussed, Minogue identifies two primary functions of ideology. First, it involves falsification, whereby societies are critiqued and portrayed as inherently flawed. Through this process of criticism, the second function of ideology emerges: revelation. This revelation consists of two aspects—the recognition that individuals exist within an oppressive system and the provision of knowledge on how to liberate individuals from this situation.

  According to Minogue, the problem with ideology lies in two main aspects. First, it identifies the oppressive system as the modern West with its individualistic tendencies. Second, ideologies are considered by their devotees to be apolitical because they falsely claim to possess a revealed truth that places them outside the realm of political discourse. Disagreement and conflict are inevitable in political discourse, yet ideologues consider them dangerous to the harmonious society comprised of emancipated individuals. Consequently, in the ideological utopia, politics would be abolished as it is deemed counterproductive to the achievement of this new world, rendering it unnecessary.

  This diversion into Minogues concept of ideology is crucial as it serves as a foundation for understanding his pointed critique of Scruton. This critique is evident in Minogues personal papers housed at the Institute of Intellectual History at St Andrews, where Minogue writes about Scrutons conservatism:

  Dr. Scruton, far from respecting the logic of party, has presented an account of conservatism as if it were the only sound social philosophy. His “Dogma” is very intellectually upmarket, and can find no place for any other view except as an error, and usually as a pernicious error. He has turned conservatism into an ideology.

  The essence of Minogues critique lies in his assertion that Scruton has forsaken the principle of the logic of party, which posits that each political doctrine holds equal value in the realm of political discourse. Scruton, according to Minogue, portrays conservatism as the superior or valid doctrine, thus deviating from this principle. Minogues argument is grounded in Scrutons identification of errors within socialism and liberalism. To be fair to Scruton, he acknowledges some truth in both doctrines—socialism in the concept of mutual dependence and social membership, and liberalism in the promotion of individual liberty free from arbitrary power. However, Minogue contends that Scruton, akin to an ideologue, presents conservatism as possessing a deeper and revealed truth, which serves as a corrective doctrine to the perceived errors of socialism and liberalism.

  For Minogue, Scrutons scepticism of ideological dreams from the Left was in good order, but he failed to look inward to his own ideological inclinations.

  Minogues central concern is that this purported deeper truth is intended to guide conservative politics, which raises some problems. Firstly, it contradicts the very essence of conservatism by formalising it into a set of rigid principles. Secondly, by asserting the superiority of conservatism, it places it beyond the realm of political discourse, as Minogue puts it, leading to the annihilation of all other legitimate possibilities … and hence the abolition of modern politics altogether.

  Scruton did not intend to present conservatism in such a sense, but an analysis of the interconnected claims he makes about conservatism still supports the ideological charge. First, Scruton contends that modernity has alienated the individual I from the collective We. In response, he proposes the construction of a new political order based on a pre-political unity of the collective We. Furthermore, Scruton suggests that this pre-political unity is inherently tied to a natural order, which conservatives have privileged access to.

  The problem arises with the concept of alienation, which Scruton adopts in a non-Marxist form. Firstly, for Scruton, the primary concern facing political conservatives is the alienation engendered by Oikophobia—the disdain, rejection, or repudiation of ones home—within modernity. In contrast, Minogue argues that Scruton exaggerates the fragmented nature of individuals in the contemporary world. Second, and more significantly, the condition of alienation and the requisite pre-political unity needed to alleviate individuals plight necessitates revelatory knowledge accessible only to genuine conservatives.

  According to Minogue, in order to access this revelatory truth, Scruton has adopted the two functions of ideology. First, falsification is evident in Scrutons critique of liberal ideals and institutions as fundamentally flawed, such as their conception of the individual and the basis of political legitimacy. This led Minogue to remark that Scruton harbours a settled hostility to liberalism and even, at times, to liberty itself. Through this process, Scruton attains revelatory knowledge about the alienated condition of individuals and the means to redeem them by accessing the pre-political form of unity that serves as the foundation for political action. Consequently, in the Scrutonian worldview, politics is dichotomised into those confined in Platos cave and those who have escaped to the light.

  In asserting a revealed truth, Scruton has effectively transformed conservatism into an ideology. This transformation brings forth the second charge that Minogue levies against Scruton, which is that his account of conservatism falls outside the tradition found in Britain. Minogue writes,

  What Dr. Scruton [conservatism] has done is to fossilize an important aspect of Conservatism and the British tradition (namely, its respect for existing communities and arrangements) into the dream of a regulated utopia (cohesive families and aesthetic regulations) which is not only impossible but, in many respects, untrue to the Anglo-Saxon Tradition.

  Their disagreement lies in their respective interpretations of the British way of life. Scruton focuses on nurturing communal bonds through the practices and institutions of Britain, emphasising their role in sustaining societal cohesion. While Minogue acknowledges the value of these communal bonds as conditions of freedom, he contends that Scruton has dispatched with the belief that individualism is at the heart of Britains condition of freedom. According to Minogue, individualism, as a moral practice inherent in Britain, allows individuals to pursue their felicity and moral identity within an orderly civil association. This individualistic ethos not only underpins Britains condition of freedom but also fosters its peoples vitality, richness, spirit, entrepreneurship, and other dimensions of societal flourishing.

  Scruton further distances himself from the British tradition through the ideological nature of his conservatism. Conservative thinkers like Nöel OSullivan and Anthony Quinton have argued that the core of British conservatism is the recognition of the imperfection of human conduct, which necessitates a restrained style of politics. Minogue argues that Scruton departs from this tradition by imposing undue expectations on politics. Scrutons heightened demands on politics stem from his identification of the primary challenge facing political conservatives in modern times and his proposed solution. As mentioned earlier, Scruton regards the central concern for political conservatives as the alienation of the “I” from the “We.” Consequently, political conservatives feel compelled to embark on a salvational endeavour aimed at liberating the individual from this predicament. This can be achieved through an expansive view of legitimate political action, which involves the coercive power of the state guided by the revealed truth that Scruton has discovered.

  Minogue identifies asking too much from politics as one aspect of the problem, which is interconnected with another issue: Scrutons misidentification of the primary challenge facing political conservatism. In Minogue’s view, this challenge revolves around the divorce of individualism from its essential prerequisite of authority, resulting in the proliferation of impulsive conduct. This divorce originates from the ideological assault on authoritative conditions for human conduct, beginning with the rule of law, which is perceived by ideologues as a tool of oppression. The dismantling of social institutions of authority, such as the family, has led, in Minogues words, to “a graveyard of inherited conventions.” Lastly, our inner authority has increasingly been supplanted by a servile mind, wherein individuals have relinquished their moral agency and autonomy. In response to this situation, Minogue suggests that political conservatives should not seek to recreate the City of God on Earth; instead, they should focus on navigating the ship steadily and keeping it afloat in the boundless ocean of modern life.

  Minogues critique raises pertinent questions about Scrutonian conservatism. However, it is important to consider that Minogues criticism of Scruton may not fully encompass the breadth, context, and evolution of Scrutons thought, especially given that Minogues critiques primarily stem from his reading of Scrutons The Meaning of Conservatism (1980). Over time, it appears that Minogues perspective on Scruton may have softened. This is noticeable in Minogues review of Mark Dooleys work on Scruton, where he expressed regret over the lack of academic attention devoted to Scrutons contributions to conservatism, despite the criticism and hostility Scruton faced from the Left. The reason could be that Minogue began to affirm the conditions of freedom in his increasing attention to social and cultural issues as Scruton did. Alternatively, Scruton himself may have moderated certain aspects of his positions that Minogue initially found problematic. Take, for example, Scruton’s book The Uses of Pessimism and the Danger of False Hope. In this work, Scruton, much like Minogues, argues that human imperfection makes the ideological belief that we can advance collectively to our goals by adopting a common plan, and by working towards it, under the leadership of some central authority such as the state, a fallacy.

  Minogue would have certainly not disagreed with Scruton’s acknowledgment of the ideological fallacy. The problem that Scruton failed to understand was what Minogue noted:

  The main danger besetting the conservative is that he may become so enchanted with the particular things that he finds suitable for conservation at his particular time that he will begin to construct a fixed ideology-a static blueprint of a good society.

  For Minogue, Scrutons scepticism of ideological dreams from the Left was in good order, but he failed to look inward at his own ideological inclinations. This ideological inclination raises the key question: the viability of Scrutonian-inspired conservatism as a guiding philosophy for the future of conservative politics. From Minogues standpoint, the answer seems to be negative. However, the broader question remains: can Minogue-inspired conservatism fill this role? Well, when comparing name recognition, fame, adulation, and attractiveness to the conservative masses of both, it appears this question has already been answered.

Comments
Welcome to mreligion comments! Please keep conversations courteous and on-topic. To fosterproductive and respectful conversations, you may see comments from our Community Managers.
Sign up to post
Sort by
Show More Comments
RELIGION & LIBERTY
Adam Smith and the Poor
Adam Smith did not seem to think that riches were requisite to happiness: “the beggar, who suns himself by the side of the highway, possesses that security which kings are fighting for” (The Theory of Moral Sentiments). But he did not mend beggary. The beggar here is not any beggar, but Diogenes the Cynic, who asked of Alexander the Great only to step back so as not to cast a shadow upon Diogenes as he reclined alongside the highway....
Spurgeon and the Poverty-Fighting Church
Religion & Liberty: Volume 33, Number 4 Spurgeon and the Poverty-Fighting Church by Christopher Parr • October 30, 2023 Portrait of Charles Spurgeon by Alexander Melville (1885) Charles Spurgeon was a young, zealous 15-year-old boy when he came to faith in Christ. A letter to his mother at the time captures the enthusiasm of his newfound Christian faith: “Oh, how I wish that I could do something for Christ.” God granted that wish, as Spurgeon would e “the prince of...
Creating an Economy of Inclusion
The poor have been the main subject of concern in the whole tradition of Catholic Social Teaching. The Catholic Church talks often about a “preferential option for the poor.” In recent years, many of the Church’s social teaching documents have been particularly focused on the needs of the poorest people in the world’s poorest countries. The first major analysis of this topic could be said to have been in the papal encyclical Populorum Progressio, published in 1967 by Pope...
Jesus and Class Warfare
Plenty of Marxists have turned to the New Testament and the origins of Christianity. Memorable examples include the works of F.D. Maurice and Zhu Weizhi’s Jesus the Proletarian. After criticizing how so many translations of the New Testament soften Jesus’ teachings regarding material possessions, greed, and wealth, Orthodox theologian David Bentley Hart has gone so far to ask, “Are Christians supposed to be Communists?” In the Huffington Post, Dan Arel has even claimed that “Jesus was clearly a Marxist,...
Conversation Starters with … Anne Bradley
Anne Bradley is an Acton affiliate scholar, the vice president of academic affairs at The Fund for American Studies, and professor of economics at The Institute of World Politics. There’s much talk about mon good capitalism” these days, especially from the New Right. Is this long overdue, that a hyper-individualism be beaten back, or is it merely cover for increasing state control of the economy? Let me begin by saying that I hate “capitalism with adjectives” in general. This...
Lord Jonathan Sacks: The West’s Rabbi
In October 1798, the president of the United States wrote to officers of the Massachusetts militia, acknowledging a limitation of federal rule. “We have no government,” John Adams wrote, “armed with power capable of contending with human passions unbridled by morality and religion. Avarice, ambition, and revenge or gallantry, would break the strongest cords of our Constitution as a whale goes through a net.” The nation that Adams had helped to found would require the parts of the body...
How Dispensationalism Got Left Behind
Whether we like it or not, Americans, in one way or another, have all been indelibly shaped by dispensationalism. Such is the subtext of Daniel Hummel’s provocative telling of the rise and fall of dispensationalism in America. In a little less than 350 pages, Hummel traces how a relatively insignificant Irishman from the Plymouth Brethren, John Nelson Darby, prompted the proliferation of dispensational theology, especially its eschatology, or theology of the end times, among our ecclesiastical, cultural, and political...
Up from the Liberal Founding
During the 20th century, scholars of the American founding generally believed that it was liberal. Specifically, they saw the founding as rooted in the political thought of 17th-century English philosopher John Locke. In addition, they saw Locke as a primarily secular thinker, one who sought to isolate the role of religion from political considerations except when necessary to prop up the various assumptions he made for natural rights. These included a divine creator responsible for a rational world for...
Mistaken About Poverty
Perhaps it is because America is the land of liberty and opportunity that debates about poverty are especially intense in the United States. Americans and would-be Americans have long been told that if they work hard enough and persevere they can achieve their dreams. For many people, the mere existence of poverty—absolute or relative—raises doubts about that promise and the American experiment more generally. Is it true that America suffers more poverty than any other advanced democracy in the...
C.S. Lewis and the Apocalypse of Gender
From very nearly the beginning, Christianity has wrestled with the question of the body. Heretics from gnostics to docetists devalued physical reality and the body, while orthodox Christianity insisted that the physical world offers us true signs pointing to God. This quarrel persists today, and one form it takes is the general confusion among Christians and non-Christians alike about gender. Is gender an abstracted idea? Is it reducible to biological characteristics? Is it a set of behaviors determined by...
Related Classification
Copyright 2023-2024 - www.mreligion.com All Rights Reserved