Home
/
RELIGION & LIBERTY
/
Democracy Does Not Ensure Liberty
Democracy Does Not Ensure Liberty
Oct 5, 2024 1:36 PM

Eighty years ago, Woodrow Wilson took America into the twentieth century with a challenge to make the world safe for democracy. As we enter the twenty-first century, our task is to make democracy safe for the world”: the very significance of Fareed Zakaria’s The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at Home and Abroad is condensed in its brilliant last paragraph. Dr. Zakaria, who is the editor of Newsweek International and a mentator, is not the first who tries plete the geography of the limits and restrains to be imposed on this peculiar form of government.

This effort has been one of the topoi of classical liberalism in the last two centuries: classical liberals were not that much concerned with the question “how many people are choosing the rulers?” (democracy), but rather with the question “how should political power be restrained in order to patible with individual freedom?” (liberty). Zakaria goes back to the underpinning of plex tradition of thought to demonstrate that es not from politicians’ slavish obeisance to the whims of the people. es only thanks to an intricate architecture of liberty, which basically consists of a whole set of institutions that counterbalance central power.

The Future of Freedom is an eloquent defense of constitutional liberalism over mere majority rule, and it could not e on the scene at a more appropriate time. Democracy—a procedural rule based upon frequent elections in a regime of universal franchise—is not per se the habitat of freedom. “For people in the West,” Zakaria writes, “democracy means ‘liberal democracy’: a political system marked not only by free and fair elections but also by the rule of law, a separation of powers, and the protection of basic liberties of speech, assembly, religion, and property. But this bundle of freedoms—what might be termed ‘constitutional liberal’—has nothing intrinsically to do with democracy and the two have not always gone together, even in the West.” The fact that some modern dictatorships sprang from the “will of the people” is well known and acknowledged by Zakaria. But, in a sense, that does not surprise him: “constitutional liberalism,” he writes, “is not about the procedures for selecting government but, rather, government’s goals.”

Political institutions should be evaluated not just for the goals they are pursuing—but for their efficiency in pursuing those very goals. That liberal constitutionalism has been enough for preserving individual freedom is a questionable proposition, and indeed that has been questioned by a relevant number of scholars. The renowned scholar Anthony de pared constitutions with a chastity belt intended to restrain political libido. But, he famously pointed out, “With its key always within reach, a chastity belt will at best delay before nature takes its course.”

This metaphor reminds us that political constitutions are nevertheless written by human hands. Legislators have the power of writing and possibly re-writing and changing them. In an enlightening page of his On Power, Bertrand de Jouvenel quotes John of Salisbury’s venerable distinction between tyranny and kingship. “Between a tyrant and a prince,” he wrote in the Policraticus, “there is this single or chief difference, that the latter obeys the law and rules the people by its dictates, accounting himself as but their servant.” This dichotomy was truly intelligible to the medieval man, who firmly believed that a law that was independent of political power, written in the sky and engraved in human hearts, truly existed. But modernity is fuelled by secularization: in our times, political authority must be not merely the enforcer of natural or consuetudinary law, but rather the producer of law.

Zakaria is right when he writes: “legitimacy is the elixir of political power .… Only democracy has that authority in the world today.” But although democracy is perceived by most as a sufficient guarantee for individual liberty, that does not prove it really is. In a sense, The Future of Freedom is all about this point. Nevertheless, Zakaria merely substitutes constitutionalism for democracy and maintains that it is necessary to preserve liberty without questioning constitutionalism’s own doctrinaire legitimization. Constitutionalism raises questions that deserve to be answered in detail.

Zakaria simply does not ask himself if constitutionalism is either theoretically consistent or historically efficient in preserving freedom. This fact, although being somewhat excusable in a book written for laypeople, constitutes a serious problem in the logical structure of the The Future of Freedom.

Zakaria understands perfectly what the spirit of a liberal constitution is: “Constitutions,” he writes, “were also meant to tame the passions of the public, creating not simply democratic but deliberative governments.” Fair enough, but did they succeed?

Zakaria provides a negative answer indirectly when examining the growth of government in recent years. “Since the early 1980s, three Republican presidents … one Republican speaker, and one Democrat president have tried to pare down government spending. But they bumped up against the reality of interest-group power. As a result, in eight years Reagan was able to close exactly four government programs of any note.”

Zakaria’s account of the “tyranny of the status quo” focuses more on the power of vested interest than it does on institutional reasons. That is an unfortunate deficiency, because the book itself deals greatly with the different performances of several institutional frameworks. What is truly valuable, in this analysis, is the role that Zakaria acknowledges for decentralization per se(and, so, its instrumentality in making democracy safer for the world).

For example, he recounts an interesting episode, well known to the scholars of the Austrian Empire. “That March [1895] Vienna had elected an ultranationalist, Karl Lueger, as mayor. Lueger’s politics were ugly. He regularly likened Jews to locusts, demanding that they be crushed into the ground like fertilizer or packed onto ships and drowned at sea. The Habsburg emperor, Franz Joseph I, decided that Lueger’s election was a threat to the city’s civic liberty and, in an unprecedented move, refused to honor it.” This was indeed, as Zakaria sharply notes, a celebration of “liberty against democracy” (emphasis added).

The late Erik von Kuehnelt-Leddihn told the story of Theodore Roosevelt calling on Emperor Franz Joseph and asking what possible point there could be to an emperor in the modern 20th century. Franz Joseph replied: “To protect my peoples from their governments.” We could not possibly know if the great Emperor implied that, vice versa, a democracy did not know of such a protection.

It could be. But what made the Habsburgs’ empire a still peerless institution, which had the great merit of preserving freedom for its citizen vis-à-vis the ing menace of nationalism (and, indeed, vis-à-vis the liberals who preached nationalism at those times), is not monarchy per se. Rather, it is the fact that the Habsburg monarchy fit into a scheme of mutually limiting powers that made it impossible for a homogeneous central authority to take over.

Zakaria acknowledges this fact, and actually his account of the birth of freedom in the West is mostly Actonian. He follows Benjamin Constant’s footsteps in distinguishing between the freedom perceived by the ancients and by the moderns: the latter being basically a negative freedom, not just the liberty to take a part in the government of the polis (as Ancient, Greek-democratic eleutheria was). Then, he reflects on what he calls “the paradox of Catholicism”: “The church never saw itself as furthering individual liberty, but from the start it tenaciously opposed the power of the state and thus placed limits on monarchs’ rule …. The Catholic Church was the first major institution in history that was independent of temporal authority and willing to challenge it. By doing this it cracked the edifice of state power, and in nooks and crannies individual liberty began to grow.”

That is neither new nor is it original, but it is indeed interesting how Zakaria seeks to popularize certain findings and studies still both unknown to a larger audience and opposed by the Straussian neo-conservatives.

Nevertheless, Zakaria seems to believe that, although the Popes’ actions unintentionally produced a higher degree of freedom, the Catholic Church is inherently an institution with little concern for individual liberty. There is really no parison between the church and political power. The Church is a voluntary organization: people who belong to it can freely exercise their right to exit. The Church’s authority is moral, not political, and people subscribe to it without being coerced by anyone. We do not have to tithe to our bishops, but we must pay taxes to our politicians: this key fact is missed in Zakaria’s analysis. Similarly, some may have doubts about his understanding of the market economy. He often pays lip service to private property and the market, but he does not seem to fully grasp their significance for personal freedom.

Even so, now that democracy has e a sacred cow, The Future of Freedom offers a e challenge to mainstream, established opinions. Zakaria’s brave effort to distinguish between majority rule and individual freedom deserves to be carefully pondered.

Comments
Welcome to mreligion comments! Please keep conversations courteous and on-topic. To fosterproductive and respectful conversations, you may see comments from our Community Managers.
Sign up to post
Sort by
Show More Comments
RELIGION & LIBERTY
C.S. Lewis and the Apocalypse of Gender
From very nearly the beginning, Christianity has wrestled with the question of the body. Heretics from gnostics to docetists devalued physical reality and the body, while orthodox Christianity insisted that the physical world offers us true signs pointing to God. This quarrel persists today, and one form it takes is the general confusion among Christians and non-Christians alike about gender. Is gender an abstracted idea? Is it reducible to biological characteristics? Is it a set of behaviors determined by...
Adam Smith and the Poor
Adam Smith did not seem to think that riches were requisite to happiness: “the beggar, who suns himself by the side of the highway, possesses that security which kings are fighting for” (The Theory of Moral Sentiments). But he did not mend beggary. The beggar here is not any beggar, but Diogenes the Cynic, who asked of Alexander the Great only to step back so as not to cast a shadow upon Diogenes as he reclined alongside the highway....
Spurgeon and the Poverty-Fighting Church
Religion & Liberty: Volume 33, Number 4 Spurgeon and the Poverty-Fighting Church by Christopher Parr • October 30, 2023 Portrait of Charles Spurgeon by Alexander Melville (1885) Charles Spurgeon was a young, zealous 15-year-old boy when he came to faith in Christ. A letter to his mother at the time captures the enthusiasm of his newfound Christian faith: “Oh, how I wish that I could do something for Christ.” God granted that wish, as Spurgeon would e “the prince of...
Creating an Economy of Inclusion
The poor have been the main subject of concern in the whole tradition of Catholic Social Teaching. The Catholic Church talks often about a “preferential option for the poor.” In recent years, many of the Church’s social teaching documents have been particularly focused on the needs of the poorest people in the world’s poorest countries. The first major analysis of this topic could be said to have been in the papal encyclical Populorum Progressio, published in 1967 by Pope...
Lord Jonathan Sacks: The West’s Rabbi
In October 1798, the president of the United States wrote to officers of the Massachusetts militia, acknowledging a limitation of federal rule. “We have no government,” John Adams wrote, “armed with power capable of contending with human passions unbridled by morality and religion. Avarice, ambition, and revenge or gallantry, would break the strongest cords of our Constitution as a whale goes through a net.” The nation that Adams had helped to found would require the parts of the body...
Conversation Starters with … Anne Bradley
Anne Bradley is an Acton affiliate scholar, the vice president of academic affairs at The Fund for American Studies, and professor of economics at The Institute of World Politics. There’s much talk about mon good capitalism” these days, especially from the New Right. Is this long overdue, that a hyper-individualism be beaten back, or is it merely cover for increasing state control of the economy? Let me begin by saying that I hate “capitalism with adjectives” in general. This...
Jesus and Class Warfare
Plenty of Marxists have turned to the New Testament and the origins of Christianity. Memorable examples include the works of F.D. Maurice and Zhu Weizhi’s Jesus the Proletarian. After criticizing how so many translations of the New Testament soften Jesus’ teachings regarding material possessions, greed, and wealth, Orthodox theologian David Bentley Hart has gone so far to ask, “Are Christians supposed to be Communists?” In the Huffington Post, Dan Arel has even claimed that “Jesus was clearly a Marxist,...
How Dispensationalism Got Left Behind
Whether we like it or not, Americans, in one way or another, have all been indelibly shaped by dispensationalism. Such is the subtext of Daniel Hummel’s provocative telling of the rise and fall of dispensationalism in America. In a little less than 350 pages, Hummel traces how a relatively insignificant Irishman from the Plymouth Brethren, John Nelson Darby, prompted the proliferation of dispensational theology, especially its eschatology, or theology of the end times, among our ecclesiastical, cultural, and political...
Up from the Liberal Founding
During the 20th century, scholars of the American founding generally believed that it was liberal. Specifically, they saw the founding as rooted in the political thought of 17th-century English philosopher John Locke. In addition, they saw Locke as a primarily secular thinker, one who sought to isolate the role of religion from political considerations except when necessary to prop up the various assumptions he made for natural rights. These included a divine creator responsible for a rational world for...
Mistaken About Poverty
Perhaps it is because America is the land of liberty and opportunity that debates about poverty are especially intense in the United States. Americans and would-be Americans have long been told that if they work hard enough and persevere they can achieve their dreams. For many people, the mere existence of poverty—absolute or relative—raises doubts about that promise and the American experiment more generally. Is it true that America suffers more poverty than any other advanced democracy in the...
Related Classification
Copyright 2023-2024 - www.mreligion.com All Rights Reserved